Einstein鈥檚 Third Paradise
Historians of modern science have good reason to be grateful to Paul Arthur Schilpp, professor of philosophy and Methodist clergyman but better known as the editor of a series of volumes on 鈥淟iving Philosophers,鈥 which included several volumes on scientist-philosophers. His motto was: 鈥淭he asking of questions about a philosopher鈥檚 meaning while he is alive.鈥 And to his everlasting credit, he persuaded Albert Einstein to do what he had resisted all his years: to sit down to write, in 1946 at age sixty-seven, an extensive autobiography 鈥揻orty-five pages long in print.
To be sure, Einstein excluded there most of what he called 鈥渢he merely personal.鈥 But on the very first page he shared a memory that will guide us to the main conclusion of this essay. He wrote that when still very young, he had searched for an escape from the seemingly hopeless and demoralizing chase after one鈥檚 desires and strivings. That escape offered itself first in religion. Although brought up as the son of 鈥渆ntirely irreligious (Jewish) parents,鈥 through the teaching in his Catholic primary school, mixed with his private instruction in elements of the Jewish religion, Einstein found within himself a 鈥渄eep religiosity鈥濃搃ndeed, 鈥渢he religious paradise of youth.鈥
The accuracy of this memorable experience is documented in other sources, including the biographical account of Einstein鈥檚 sister, Maja. There she makes a plausible extrapolation: that Einstein鈥檚 鈥渞eligious feeling鈥 found expression in later years in his deep interest and actions to ameliorate the difficulties to which fellow Jews were being subjected, actions ranging from his fights against anti-Semitism to his embrace of Zionism (in the hope, as he put it in one of his speeches [April 20, 1935], that it would include a 鈥減eaceable and friendly cooperation with the Arab people鈥). As we shall see, Maja鈥檚 extrapolation of the reach of her brother鈥檚 early religious feelings might well have gone much further.
The primacy of young Albert鈥檚 First Paradise came to an abrupt end. As he put it early in his 鈥淎utobiographical Notes,鈥 through reading popular science books he came to doubt the stories of the Bible. Thus he passed first through what he colorfully described as a 鈥減ositively fanatic indulgence in free thinking.鈥1 But then he found new enchantments. First, at age twelve, he read a little book on Euclidean plane geometry鈥 he called it 鈥渉oly,鈥 a veritable 鈥淲under.鈥 Then, still as a boy, he became entranced by the contemplation of that huge external, extra-personal world of science, which presented itself to him 鈥渓ike a great, eternal riddle.鈥 To that study one could devote oneself, finding thereby 鈥渋nner freedom and security.鈥 He believed that choosing the 鈥渞oad to this Paradise,鈥 although quite antithetical to the first one and less alluring, did prove itself trustworthy. Indeed, by age sixteen, he had his father declare him to the authorities as 鈥渨ithout confession,鈥 and for the rest of his life he tried to dissociate himself from organized religious activities and associations, inventing his own form of religiousness, just as he was creating his own physics.
These two realms appeared to him eventually not as separate as numerous biographers would suggest. On the contrary, my task here is to demonstrate that at the heart of Einstein鈥檚 mature identity there developed a fusion of his First and his Second Paradise鈥搃nto a Third Paradise, where the meaning of a life of brilliant scientific activity drew on the remnants of his fervent first feelings of youthful religiosity.
For this purpose, we shall have to make what may seem like an excursus, but one that will in the end throw light on his overwhelming passion, throughout his scientific and personal life, to bring about the joining of these and other seemingly incommensurate aspects, whether in nature or society. In 1918 he gave a glimpse of it in a speech (鈥Prinzipien der Forschung鈥) honoring the sixtieth birthday of his friend and colleague Max Planck, to whose rather metaphysical conception about the purpose of science Einstein had drifted while moving away from the quite opposite, positivistic one of an early intellectual mentor, Ernst Mach. As Einstein put it in that speech, the search for one 鈥渟implified and lucid image of the world鈥 not only was the supreme task for a scientist, but also corresponded to a psychological need: to flee from personal, everyday life, with all its dreary disappointments, and escape into the world of objective perception and thought. Into the formation of such a world picture the scientist could place the 鈥渃enter of gravity of his emotional life [骋别蹿眉丑濒蝉濒别产别苍].鈥 And in a sentence with special significance, he added that persevering on the most difficult scientific problems requires 鈥渁 state of feeling [骋别蹿眉丑濒蝉锄耻蝉迟补苍诲] similar to that of a religious person or a lover.鈥
Throughout Einstein鈥檚 writings, one can watch him searching for that world picture, for a comprehensive Weltanschauung, one yielding a total conception that, as he put it, would include every empirical fact (Gesamtheit der Erfahrungstatsachen)鈥搉ot only of physical science, but also of life.
Einstein was of course not alone in this pursuit. The German literature of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries contained a seemingly obsessive flood of books and essays on the oneness of the world picture. They included writings by both Ernst Mach and Max Planck, and, for good measure, a 1912 general manifesto appealing to scholars in all fields of knowledge to combine their efforts in order to 鈥渂ring forth a comprehensive Weltanschauung.鈥 The thirty-four signatories included Ernst Mach, Sigmund Freud, Ferdinand T枚nnies, David Hilbert, Jacques Loeb鈥 and the then still little-known Albert Einstein.
But while for most others this culturally profound longing for unity鈥揳lready embedded in the philosophical and literary works they all had studied鈥搘as mostly the subject of an occasional opportunity for exhortation (nothing came of the manifesto), for Einstein it was different, a constant preoccupation responding to a persistent, deeply felt intellectual and psychological need.
This fact can be most simply illustrated in Einstein鈥檚 scientific writings. As a first example, I turn to one of my favorite manuscripts in his archive. It is a lengthy manuscript in his handwriting, of around 1920, titled, in translation, 鈥淔undamental Ideas and Methods of Relativity.鈥 It contains the passage in which Einstein revealed what in his words was 鈥渢he happiest thought of my life [der gluecklichste Gedanke meines Lebens]鈥濃揳 thought experiment that came to him in 1907: nothing less than the definition of the equivalence principle, later developed in his general relativity theory. It occurred to Einstein鈥 thinking first of all in visual terms, as was usual for him鈥搕hat if a man were falling from the roof of his house and tried to let anything drop, it would only move alongside him, thus indicating the equivalence of acceleration and gravity. In Einstein鈥檚 words, 鈥渢he acceleration of free fall with respect to the material is therefore a mighty argument that the postulate of relativity is to be extended to coordinate systems that move nonuniformly relative to one another . . . . 鈥
For the present purpose I want to draw attention to another passage in that manuscript. His essay begins in a largely impersonal, pedagogic tone, similar to that of his first popular book on relativity, published in 1917. But in a surprising way, in the section titled 鈥淕eneral Relativity Theory,鈥 Einstein suddenly switches to a personal account. He reports that in the construction of the special theory, the 鈥渢hought concerning the Faraday [experiment] on electromagnetic induction played for me a leading role.鈥 He then describes that old experiment, in words similar to the first paragraph of his 1905 relativity paper, concentrating on the well-known fact, discovered by Faraday in 1831, that the induced current is the same whether it is the coil or the magnet that is in motion relative to the other, whereas the 鈥渢heoretical interpretation of the phenomenon in these two cases is quite different.鈥 While other physicists, for many decades, had been quite satisfied with that difference, here Einstein reveals a central preoccupation at the depth of his soul: 鈥淭he thought that one is dealing here with two fundamentally different cases was for me unbearable [war mir unertraeglich]. The difference between these two cases could not be a real difference . . . . The phenomenon of the electromagnetic induction forced me to postulate the (special) relativity principle.鈥
Let us step back for a moment to contemplate that word 鈥渦nbearable.鈥 It is reinforced by a passage in Einstein鈥檚 鈥淎utobiographical Notes鈥: 鈥淏y and by I despaired [verzweifelte ich] of discovering the true laws by means of constructive efforts based on known facts. The longer and the more despairingly I tried, the more I came to the conviction that only the discovery of a universal formal principle could lead us to assured results.鈥 He might have added that the same postulational method had already been pioneered in their main works by two of his heroes, Euclid and Newton.
Other physicists, for example Bohr and Heisenberg, also reported that at times they were brought to despair in their research. Still other scientists were evidently even brought to suicide by such disappointment. For researchers fiercely engaged at the very frontier, the psychological stakes can be enormous. Einstein was able to resolve his discomfort by turning, as he did in his 1905 relativity paper, to the postulation of two formal principles (the principle of relativity throughout physics, and the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuo), and adopting such postulation as one of his tools of thought.
Einstein also had a second method to bridge the unbearable differences in a theory: generalizing it, so that the apparently differently grounded phenomena are revealed to be coming from the same base. We know from a letter to Max von Laue of January 17, 1952, found in the archive, that Einstein鈥檚 early concern with the physics of fluctuation phenomena was the common root of his three great papers of 1905, on such different topics as the quantum property of light, Brownian movement, and relativity. But even earlier, in a letter of April 14, 1901, to his school friend Marcel Grossmann, Einstein had revealed his generalizing approach to physics while working on his very first published paper, on capillarity. There he tried to bring together in one theory the opposing behaviors of bodies: moving upward when a liquid is in a capillary tube, but downward when the liquid is released freely. In that letter, he spelled out his interpenetrating emotional and scientific needs in one sentence: 鈥淚t is a wonderful feeling [ein herrliches Gef眉hl] to recognize the unity of a complex of appearances which, to direct sense experiences, appear to be quite separate things.鈥
The postulation of universal formal principles, and the discovery among phenomena of a unity, of Einheitlichkeit, through the generalization of the basic theory鈥搕hose were two of Einstein鈥檚 favorite weapons,2 as his letters and manuscripts show. Writing to Willem de Sitter on November 4, 1916, he confessed: 鈥淚 am driven by my need to generalize [mein Verallgemeinerungsbeduerfnis].鈥 That need, that compulsion, was also deeply entrenched in German culture and resonated with, and supported, Einstein鈥檚 approach. Let me just note in passing that while still a student at the Polytechnic Institute in Zurich, in order to get his certificate to be a high school science teacher, Einstein took optional courses on Immanuel Kant and Goethe, whose central works he had studied since his teenage years.
That Verallgemeinerungsbeduerfnis was clearly a driving force behind Einstein鈥檚 career trajectory. Thus he generalized from old experimental results, like Faraday鈥檚, to arrive at special relativity, in which he unified space and time, electric and magnetic forces, energy and mass, and so resolved the whole long dispute among scientists between adherence to a mechanistic versus an electromagnetic world picture. Then he generalized the special theory to produce what he first significantly called, in an article of 1913, not the general but the generalized relativity theory. Paul Ehrenfest wrote him in puzzlement: 鈥淗ow far will this Verallgemeinerung go on?鈥 And, finally, Einstein threw himself into the attempt of a grand unification of quantum physics and of gravity: a unified field theory. It is an example of an intense and perhaps unique, life-long, tenacious dedication, despite Einstein鈥檚 failure at the very end 鈥搘hich nevertheless, as a program, set the stage for the ambition of some of today鈥檚 best scientists, who have taken over that search for the Holy Grail of physics鈥揳 theory of everything.
So much for trying to get a glimpse of the mind of Einstein as scientist. But at this point, for anyone who has studied this man鈥檚 work and life in detail, a new thought urges itself forward. As in his science, Einstein also lived under the compulsion to unify鈥搃n his politics, in his social ideals, even in his everyday behavior. He abhorred all nationalisms, and called himself, even while in Berlin during World War I, a European. Later he supported the One World movement, dreamed of a unified supernational form of government, helped to initiate the international Pugwash movement of scientists during the Cold War, and was as ready to befriend visiting high school students as the Queen of the Belgians. His instinctive penchant for democracy and dislike of hierarchy and class differences must have cost him greatly in the early days, as when he addressed his chief professor at the Swiss Polytechnic Institute, on whose recommendation his entrance to any academic career would depend, not by any title, but simply as 鈥淗err Weber.鈥 And at the other end of the spectrum, in his essay on ethics, Einstein cited Moses, Jesus, and Buddha as equally valid prophets.
No boundaries, no barriers; none in life, as there are none in nature. Einstein鈥檚 life and his work were so mutually resonant that we recognize both to have been carried on together in the service of one grand project鈥搕he fusion into one coherency.
There were also no boundaries or barriers between Einstein鈥檚 scientific and religious feelings. After having passed from the youthful first, religious paradise into his second, immensely productive scientific one, he found in his middle years a fusion of those two motivations鈥揾is Third Paradise.
We had a hint of this development in his remark in 1918, where he observed the parallel states of feeling of the scientist and of the 鈥渞eligious person.鈥 Other hints come from the countless, well-known quotations in which Einstein referred to God鈥揹oing it so often that Niels Bohr had to chide him. Karl Popper remarked that in conversations with Einstein, 鈥淚 learned nothing . . . . he tended to express things in theological terms, and this was often the only way to argue with him. I found it finally quite uninteresting.鈥
But two other reports may point to the more profound layer of Einstein鈥檚 deepest convictions. One is his remark to one of his assistants, Ernst Straus: 鈥淲hat really interests me is whether God had any choice in the creation of the world.鈥 The second is Einstein鈥檚 reply to a curious telegram.
In 1929, Boston鈥檚 Cardinal O鈥機onnell branded Einstein鈥檚 theory of relativity as 鈥渂efogged speculation producing universal doubt about God and His Creation,鈥 and as implying 鈥渢he ghastly apparition of atheism.鈥 In alarm, New York鈥檚 Rabbi Herbert S. Goldstein asked Einstein by telegram: 鈥淒o you believe in God? Stop. Answer paid 50 words.鈥 In his response, for which Einstein needed but twenty-five (German) words, he stated his beliefs succinctly: 鈥淚 believe in Spinoza鈥檚 God, Who reveals Himself in the lawful harmony of the world, not in a God Who concerns Himself with the fate and the doings of mankind.鈥 The rabbi cited this as evidence that Einstein was not an atheist, and further declared that 鈥淓instein鈥檚 theory, if carried to its logical conclusion, would bring to mankind a scientific formula for monotheism.鈥 Einstein wisely remained silent on that point.
The good rabbi might have had in mind the writings of the Religion of Science movement, which had flourished in Germany under the distinguished auspices of Ernst Haeckel, Wilhelm Ostwald, and their circle (the Monistenbund), and also in America, chiefly in Paul Carus鈥檚 books and journals, such as The Open Court, which carried the words 鈥淒evoted to the Religion of Science鈥 on its masthead.
If Einstein had read Carus鈥檚 book, The Religion of Science (1893), he may have agreed with one sentence in it: 鈥淪cientific truth is not profane, it is sacred.鈥 Indeed, the charismatic view of science in the lives of some scientists has been the subject of much scholarly study, for example in Joseph Ben-David鈥檚 Scientific Growth (1991), and earlier in Robert K. Merton鈥檚 magisterial book of 1938, Science, Technology and Society in Seventeenth-Century England. In the section entitled 鈥淭he Integration of Religion and Science,鈥 Merton notes that among the scientists he studied, 鈥渢he religious ethic, considered as a social force, so consecrated science as to make it a highly respected and laudable focus of attention.鈥 The social scientist Bernard H. Gustin elaborated on this perception, writing that science at the highest level is charismatic because scientists devoted to such tasks are 鈥渢hought to come into contact with what is essential in the universe.鈥 I believe this is precisely why so many who knew little about Einstein鈥檚 scientific writing flocked to catch a glimpse of him and to this day feel somehow uplifted by contemplating his iconic image.
Starting in the late 1920s, Einstein became more and more serious about clarifying the relationship between his transcendental and his scientific impulses. He wrote several essays on religiosity; five of them, composed between 1930 and the early 1950s, are reproduced in his book Ideas and Opinions. In those chapters we can watch the result of a struggle that had its origins in his school years, as he developed, or rather invented, a religion that offered a union with science.
In the evolution of religion, he remarked, there were three developmental stages. At the first, 鈥渨ith primitive man it is above all fear that evokes religious notions. This 鈥榬eligion of fear鈥. . . is in an important degree stabilized by the formation of a special priestly caste鈥 that colludes with secular authority to take advantage of it for its own interest. The next step鈥撯渁dmirably illustrated in the Jewish scriptures鈥濃搘as a moral religion embodying the ethical imperative, 鈥渁 development [that] continued in the New Testament.鈥 Yet it had a fatal flaw: 鈥渢he anthropomorphic character of the concept of God,鈥 easy to grasp by 鈥渦nderdeveloped minds鈥 of the masses while freeing them of responsibility.
This flaw disappears at Einstein鈥檚 third, mature stage of religion, to which he believed mankind is now reaching and which the great spirits (he names Democritus, St. Francis of Assisi, and Spinoza) had already attained鈥搉amely, the 鈥渃osmic religious feeling鈥 that sheds all anthropomorphic elements. In describing the driving motivation toward that final, highest stage, Einstein uses the same ideas, even some of the same phrases, with which he had celebrated first his religious and then his scientific paradise: 鈥淭he individual feels the futility of human desires, and aims at the sublimity and marvelous order which reveal themselves both in nature and in the world of thought.鈥 鈥淚ndividual existence impresses him as a sort of prison, and he wants to experience the universe as a single, significant whole.鈥 Of course! Here as always, there has to be the intoxicating experience of unification. And so Einstein goes on, 鈥淚 maintain that the cosmic religious feeling is the strongest and noblest motive for scientific research . . . . A contemporary has said not unjustly that in this materialistic age of ours the serious scientific workers are the only profoundly religious people.鈥
In another of his essays on religion, Einstein points to a plausible source for his specific formulations: 鈥淭hose individuals to whom we owe the great creative achievements of science were all of them imbued with a truly religious conviction that this universe of ours is something perfect, and susceptible through the rational striving for knowledge. If this conviction had not been a strongly emotional one, and if those searching for knowledge had not been inspired by Spinoza鈥檚 amor dei intellectualis, they would hardly have been capable of that untiring devotion which alone enables man to attain his greatest achievements.鈥
I believe we can guess at the first time Einstein read Baruch Spinoza鈥檚 Ethics (Ethica Ordinae Geometrico Demonstrata), a system constructed on the Euclidean model of deductions from propositions. Soon after getting his first real job at the patent office, Einstein joined with two friends to form a discussion circle, meeting once or twice a week in what they called, with gallows humor, the Akademie Olympia. We know the list of books they read and discussed. High among them, reportedly at Einstein鈥檚 suggestion, was Spinoza鈥檚 Ethics, which he read afterwards several times more. Even when his sister Maja joined him in Princeton in later life and was confined to bed by an illness, he thought that reading a good book to her would help, and chose Spinoza鈥檚 Ethics for that purpose.
By that time Spinoza鈥檚 work and life had long been important to Einstein. He had written an introduction to a biography of Spinoza (by his son-in-law, Rudolf Kayser, 1946); he had contributed to the Spinoza Dictionary (1951); he had referred to Spinoza in many of his letters; and he had even composed a poem in Spinoza鈥檚 honor. He admired Spinoza for his independence of mind, his deterministic philosophical outlook, his skepticism about organized religion and orthodoxy鈥搘hich had resulted in his excommunication from his synagogue in 1656鈥揳nd even for his ascetic preference, which compelled him to remain in poverty and solitude to live in a sort of spiritual ecstasy, instead of accepting a professorship at the University of Heidelberg. Originally neglected, Spinoza鈥檚 Ethics, published only posthumously, profoundly influenced other thinkers, such as Friedrich Schlegel, Friedrich Schleiermacher, Goethe (who called him 鈥渙ur common saint鈥), Albert Schweitzer, and Romain Rolland (who, on reading Ethics, confessed, 鈥淚 deciphered not what he said, but what he meant to say鈥).
For Spinoza, God and nature were one (deus sive natura). True religion was based not on dogma but on a feeling for the rationality and the unity underlying all finite and temporal things, on a feeling of wonder and awe that generates the idea of God, but a God which lacks any anthropomorphic conception. As Spinoza wrote in Proposition 15 in Ethics, he opposed assigning to God 鈥渂ody and soul and being subject to passions.鈥 Hence, 鈥淕od is incorporeal鈥濃揳s had been said by others, from Maimonides on, to whom God was knowable indirectly through His creation, through nature. In other pages of Ethics, Einstein could read Spinoza鈥檚 opposition to the idea of cosmic purpose, and that he favored the primacy of the law of cause and effect鈥揳n all-pervasive determinism that governs nature and life鈥搑ather than 鈥減laying at dice,鈥 in Einstein鈥檚 famous remark. And as if he were merely paraphrasing Spinoza, Einstein wrote in 1929 that the perception in the universe of 鈥減rofound reason and beauty constitute true religiosity; in this sense, and in this sense alone, I am a deeply religious man.鈥
Much has been written about the response of Einstein鈥檚 contemporaries to his Spinozistic cosmic religion. For example, the physicist Arnold Sommerfeld recorded in Schilpp鈥檚 volume that he often felt 鈥渢hat Einstein stands in a particularly intimate relation to the God of Spinoza.鈥 But what finally most interests us here is to what degree Einstein, having reached his Third Paradise, in which his yearnings for science and religion are joined, may even have found in his own research in physics fruitful ideas emerging from that union. In fact there are at least some tantalizing parallels between passages in Spinoza鈥檚 Ethics and Einstein鈥檚 publications in cosmology鈥損arallels that the physicist and philosopher Max Jammer, in his book Einstein and Religion (1999), considers as amounting to intimate connections. For example, in Part I of Ethics (鈥淐oncerning God鈥), Proposition 29 begins: 鈥淚n nature there is nothing contingent, but all things are determined from the necessity of the divine nature to exist and act in a certain manner.鈥 Here is at least a discernible overlap with Einstein鈥檚 tenacious devotion to determinism and strict causality at the fundamental level, despite all the proofs from quantum mechanics of the reign of probabilism, at least in the subatomic realm.
There are other such parallels throughout. But what is considered by some as the most telling relationship between Spinoza鈥檚 Propositions and Einstein鈥檚 physics comes from passages such as Corollary 2 of Proposition 20: 鈥淚t follows that God is immutable or, which is the same thing, all His attributes are immutable.鈥 In a letter of September 3, 1915, to Else (his cousin and later his wife), Einstein, having read Spinoza鈥檚 Ethics again, wrote, 鈥淚 think the Ethics will have a permanent effect on me.鈥
Two years later, when he expanded his general relativity to include 鈥渃osmological considerations,鈥 Einstein found to his dismay that his system of equations did 鈥渘ot allow the hypothesis of a spatially closed-ness of the world [raeumliche Geschlossenheit].鈥 How did Einstein cure this flaw? By something he had done very rarely: making an ad hoc addition, purely for convenience: 鈥淲e can add, on the left side of the field equation a鈥揻or the time being鈥搖nknown universal constant, - 位.鈥 In fact, it seems that not much harm is done thereby. It does not change the covariance; it still corresponds with the observation of motions in the solar system (鈥渁s long as 位 is small鈥), and so forth. Moreover, the proposed new universal constant 位 also determines the average density of the universe with which it can remain in equilibrium, and provides the radius and volume of a presumed spherical universe.
Altogether a beautiful, immutable universe鈥搊ne an immutable God could be identified with. But in 1922, Alexander Friedmann showed that the equations of general relativity did allow expansion or contraction. And in 1929 Edwin Hubble found by astronomical observations the fact that the universe does expand. Thus Einstein鈥揳t least according to the physicist George Gamow鈥搑emarked that 鈥渋nserting 位 was the biggest blunder of my life.鈥
Max Jammer and the physicist John Wheeler, both of whom knew Einstein, traced his unusual ad hoc insertion of 位 , nailing down that 鈥渟patially closed-ness of the world,鈥 to a relationship between Einstein鈥檚 thoughts and Spinoza鈥檚 Propositions. They also pointed to another possible reason for it: In Spinoza鈥檚 writings, one finds the concept that God would not have made an empty world. But in an expanding universe, in the infinity of time, the density of matter would be diluted to zero in the limit. Space itself would disappear, since, as Einstein put it in 1952, 鈥淥n the basis of the general theory of relativity . . . space as opposed to 鈥榳hat fills space鈥. . . had no separate existence.鈥
Even if all of these suggestive indications of an intellectual, emotional, and perhaps even spiritual resonance between Einstein鈥檚 and Spinoza鈥檚 writings were left entirely aside, there still remains Einstein鈥檚 attachment to his 鈥渃osmic religion.鈥 That was the end point of his own troublesome pilgrimage in religiosity鈥揻rom his early vision of his First Paradise, through his disillusionments, to his dedication to find fundamental unity within natural science, and at last to his recognition of science as the devotion, in his words, of 鈥渁 deeply religious unbeliever鈥濃揾is final embrace of seeming incommensurables in his Third Paradise.