亚色影库app

An open access publication of the 亚色影库app & Sciences
Spring 2008

on philosophy as a guide to well-being

Author
Richard Kraut
View PDF

Fellow of the American Academy since 2006, is Charles and Emma Morrison Professor in the Humanities at Northwestern University. His publications include 鈥淪ocrates and the State鈥 (1984), 鈥淎ristotle on the Human Good鈥 (1989), and 鈥淎ristotle: Political Philosophy鈥 (2002). His most recent book is 鈥淲hat is Good and Why: The Ethics of Well-Being鈥 (2007).

Philosophers disagree about whether philosophy can teach us much about human well-being. A long Western tradition, whose roots lie in Plato and Aristotle, holds that philosophical methods, skillfully and wisely deployed, can yield substantive conclusions about what is ultimately worthwhile. For example, according to Aristotle, the best sort of life for a human being will assign a central place to activities that make excellent use of practical reason and the social emotions that are responsive to reason.

One of the distinguishing features of the modern period in philosophy is the abandonment, by some of its most important figures, of that high ambition for moral theory. Thomas Hobbes provides a striking example. In Leviathan, he says: 鈥淭here is no such finis ultimus, utmost aim, nor summum bonum, greatest good, as is spoken of in the books of the old moral philosophers.鈥 His point is that philosophical reflection is powerless to pass judgment on the worth of someone鈥檚 ultimate aims; they therefore cannot be found defective, except insofar as they might conflict with each other. As he says, 鈥淲hatsoever is the object of any man鈥檚 appetite or desires, that is it which he for his part calleth good.鈥 There is no basis, he thinks, for criticizing 鈥渢he object of any man鈥檚 appetites,鈥 and so we must let stand that man鈥檚 designation of that object as good.

The idea that there is no standard for the assessment of ultimate aims鈥搒ome rational method for deciding which among them are good and which bad鈥 became the orthodoxy of the modern period. 鈥淯ltimate ends . . . can never . . . be accounted for by reason,鈥 David Hume says in An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Similarly, when in Utilitarianism J. S. Mill asks, 鈥淲hat proof is it possible to give that pleasure is good?鈥 he replies that the only test of a thing鈥檚 desirability is the fact that it actually is desired.

All of these philosophers鈥揵oth the ancients and the moderns鈥揳re, in a sense, engaged in the task of saying what human well-being is. Their disagreement concerns whether sustained and careful reflection has a role to play in guiding human aspirations. Hobbes, like the 鈥渙ld moral philosophers鈥 he opposes, has his own answer to the question of what is good for us. He holds that what is good for someone is the satisfaction of that person鈥檚 appetites. Mill likewise argues that pleasure is the only thing that is desirable in itself, because everything we desire for itself gives us pleasure when we attain it. So Hobbes and Mill are as interested as were Plato and Aristotle in the question of what is good for human beings. But unlike their ancient predecessors, they see no room for philosophical methods to criticize the ultimate ends that someone is pursuing. Mill looks instead to the voice of discriminating experience as a guide to life: to decide which of two kinds of pleasure is more desirable, we can do nothing but determine the preferences of those who have experienced both kinds. (And if there is disagreement, he claims that the majority is more likely to be correct.)

If one wants to find, among major twentieth-century moral philosophers, defenders of a theory about what is good that is closer to the views of Plato and Aristotle than those of Hobbes, Hume, and Mill, to whom should one look? Two leading figures of the early twentieth century proposed a view that has some kinship to the classical approach to well-being. G. E. Moore (Principia Ethica) and W. D. Ross (The Right and the Good) hold that careful philosophical reflection can arrive at a conception of what is good, and that such a conception can serve as a standard that is independent of what we seek, want, or find pleasant. Ross, for example, believes that if we carefully perform a thought experiment, we will see that virtue and knowledge are good鈥搘hether or not they lead to pleasure or the satisfaction of desire. Imagine two worlds: in both, the inhabitants experience the same amount of pleasure; but in one world people possess and exercise the moral virtues, whereas in the other they are full of moral deficiencies. It is clear to our rational faculty, Ross insists, that the world containing moral virtue has a higher degree of intrinsic goodness. We can thus see that the moral virtues are indeed good, and that their goodness does not consist in their being pleasant or the objects of desire.

Unfortunately, regardless of whether we find Ross鈥檚 astonishingly simple argument persuasive, it does not really establish any thesis about what human well-being is. The topic of well-being has to do with what is good for someone. To say, for example, that being a just person is a component of well-being is simply a way of saying that if someone is just, that is good for him, not because justice is a means to something else, but even apart from its consequences. But Ross鈥檚 thought experiment does not show that justice is good for the person who has this virtue, and is not intended to do so. He, like Moore, is not interested in well-being at all. He is talking about what he calls good 鈥渟ans phrase鈥 鈥搊r what Moore sometimes called 鈥渁bsolute鈥 goodness. So they stand at some remove from the Platonic-Aristotelian tradition. They uphold the power of philosophical reflection to detect objects of aspiration that are independent of pleasure and the desires we already have. But they do not claim that possession of those objects is good for anyone. On the contrary, they think that moral philosophy would be utterly misguided to take anything but an incidental interest in whether such moral virtues as justice are good for those who possess these qualities. The question that Plato places at the heart of his Republic鈥搃s justice good for the just person?鈥搃s one they decline to address, because they do not take that to be a proper topic for moral philosophy.

Turning to the later years of the twentieth century, we find in the moral and political philosophy of John Rawls a conception of well-being whose roots lie in the modern dissenters from the classical tradition. Taking the Victorian English philosopher Henry Sidgwick as his principal guide, he holds, in A Theory of Justice, that 鈥渢he good is . . . the satisfaction of rational desire.鈥 Or, as he puts it, 鈥渁 person鈥檚 good is determined by what is for him the most rational long-term plan of life given reasonably favorable circumstances. A man is happy when he is more or less successfully in the way of carrying out his plan.鈥 The rationality of a plan is, roughly speaking, a matter of its internal consistency. Rationality is not meant to serve as a substantive basis by means of which to assess the worth of someone鈥檚 ultimate ends; it is rather a matter of the adjustment of one鈥檚 ends to each other in a coherent schedule of activities. So, for Rawls, what matters for well-being is not the content of what we pursue, but our degree of success in attaining it.

Since it can be good for someone, according to this way of thinking, to pursue goals that are normally (and rightly) regarded as morally objectionable, Rawls claims that there is a type of reason that must be given priority over what is good: moral rightness. No matter how good it may be for someone to own slaves, for example, or to violate the rights of others, the fact that it benefits him should count for nothing in our deliberations. In fact, Rawls holds that even if owning slaves did a great deal of good for a large segment of the population, that should carry no weight at all. The total amount of goodness should not be our practical goal; the utilitarian principle of good-maximization, favored by Mill, Sidgwick, and the other classical utilitarians, should not guide our personal conduct or the design of political institutions.

What Rawls has done, in effect, is to recognize that the conception of the good that guided a distinctive tradition of modern moral philosophy, from Hobbes to Sidgwick, cannot be the sole or even the principal objective of our practical thinking. We are to pursue the good (that is, the achievement of our rational plans, whatever they are), but only within the boundaries of what is right. His distinctive contribution to moral and political philosophy was to propose a standard of rightness鈥搉amely, the agreement of hypothetical contractors鈥搕hat is not itself a matter of satisfying whatever desires people happen to have. Well-being, in other words, is a reflection of our diverse individual tastes and highly variable preferences. Moral principles must therefore rest on something that does not vary so greatly from one person to another. Rawls鈥檚 affirmation of the priority of rightness over goodness stands in marked contrast to the Platonic-Aristotelian thesis that what is good for human beings must be the fundamental starting point of practical reasoning.

Rawls鈥檚 priority thesis rests on his commitment to the distinctively modern conception of well-being that runs through Hobbes, Hume, and Mill. It is because he thinks that well-being varies according to our preferences and plans that he takes goodness to be weightless in comparison with rightness. But is he right to suppose that 鈥渢he good is . . . the satisfaction of rational desire鈥? Something close to the Platonic-Aristotelian alternative continues to thrive. Derek Parfit, for example, gives, in Reasons and Persons, respectful attention to what he calls 鈥淥bjective List Theories鈥 of wellbeing, which he contrasts with 鈥淒esire-Fulfillment Theories鈥 and 鈥淗edonistic Theories.鈥 The best theory of well-being, he suggests, might be one that combines these alternatives. Such a theory might say that 鈥渨hat is good for someone is to have knowledge, to be engaged in rational activity, to experience mutual love, and to be aware of beauty, while strongly wanting just these things.鈥 That idea bears a strong similarity to Ross鈥檚 thesis that knowledge and virtue are good (although, he insists, they are good 鈥榮ans phrase鈥 rather than good for someone), and also to Aristotle鈥檚 thesis that well-being consists in excellent rational activity. What they have in common is the conviction that careful philosophical reflection can vindicate a standard, other than mere internal consistency, for assessing the value of our goals. Philosophy, so conceived, can guide the formation of our aspirations.

It should be clear that this philosophical debate has to do not with subjective well-being (that is, happiness, or a sense of fulfillment), but with objective wellbeing. All parties to it, ancient and modern, agree that we can be wrong about what is good for us. (Hobbes thought that Aristotle was wrong to conclude that what is best for us is the excellent deployment of reason and emotion.) To say that the topic under discussion is objective well-being is simply a way of expressing the commonsense thought that what someone believes about what is good for human beings could be wrong, and is not made right simply by the fact that it is believed. Subjective well-being is a fit object for psychological experiment, since it is a state of mind. But to speak of our objective wellbeing is to enter into the business of evaluating our lives. It is a normative and not a purely empirical enterprise.

The philosophical debate about wellbeing continues. James Griffin, for example, defends a theory that follows Parfit鈥檚 lead by combining elements of an 鈥淥bjective List Theory鈥 and a 鈥淒esire-Fulfillment Theory鈥 in his WellBeing: Its Meaning, Measurement, and Moral Importance. Philippa Foot proposes, in Natural Goodness, an approach to wellbeing that is consciously patterned after Aristotle鈥檚. By contrast, L. W. Sumner, in Welfare, Happiness, and Ethics, plumps for a theory that identifies wellbeing with what he calls 鈥渁uthentic happiness,鈥 and is a close relative to hedonism. My own thinking about these matters puts me firmly in the camp of Plato and Aristotle. The suggestion I make, in What is Good and Why, is that the notion of flourishing鈥搕hat is, the development and exercise of inherent biological powers鈥揷an serve as a powerful organizing idea for the articulation of a theory of well-being.