Planetary Humanities: Straddling the Decolonial/Postcolonial Divide
This essay argues that while the science of climate change treats the Earth as one, political responses to climate change are marked profoundly by the fact that humanity can never speak as one. Questions of climate justice and sustainable human futures have deepened fractured and contested histories of modernity in which the West/non-West division intersects with emergent distinctions between postcolonial and decolonial approaches. But none of these distinctions are absolute. By discussing the works of D茅borah Danowski and Eduardo Viveiros de Castro, I seek to show how traditions of European and non-European thought remain entangled even as we seek, intellectually, to decolonize the world. In a connected world, the not-one-ness of humanity acts as a ground for dissension within the humanities but not for any absolute differences.
However one looks at the difficulties of creating a politics of climate change, the question of 鈥渁nthropological difference鈥 seems to be at the root of those difficulties. Issues of 鈥渃limate justice,鈥 for instance, or those about historical responsibility for greenhouse gas emissions point, ultimately, to inequalities and power relations between rich and poor nations as well as between the rich and the poor generally, across and inside nations. What makes for a 鈥渃limate emergency鈥 is the fact that a humanity that is not one finds it difficult to respond as one to a calendar of carbon budgets and coordinated actions issued by the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), which, in effect, treats the planet as one. How to think about intrahuman differences in the face of a planet that climate scientists see as 鈥渙ne鈥 has become 鈥渢he one and the many鈥 aspect of climate politics. Sociologists Nigel Clark and Bronislaw Szerszynski have recently sought to introduce the idea of 鈥減lanetary multiplicities鈥 (by which they refer to the undeniable fact that 鈥渢he Earth has an inherent potential to shift from one state to another and to do this quickly鈥), but acknowledge the oneness of this planet by seeing it as 鈥a dynamic and self-organized鈥 entity.1 Come to think of it, all the scenarios of transition to a 鈥渮ero carbon鈥 global economy and the carbon budgets chalked up by the IPCC do not make sense unless one assumes the planet to be one. Differences between humans have therefore emerged as the truly political aspect of what the IPCC sees as a 鈥渃limate emergency.鈥2
What I wish to do in this essay is show how the humanist literature on the politics of attending to the challenges of planetary climate change draws on two contrasting ways of thinking about 鈥渕odernity鈥 and thus about differences between humans. One might broadly imagine these approaches as reflecting an emergent decolonial/postcolonial divide, a division that is, I hasten to add, by no means total. There are many connections between these approaches. They also draw, ironically but differently, on some identifiable traditions of European thought, particularly French theory after May 1968. My treatment of these approaches is necessarily partial, preliminary, exploratory, and illustrative. There are critical aspects to these approaches that I have deliberately left out of consideration for reasons of space.
Philosopher D茅borah Danowski and anthropologist Eduardo Viveiros de Castro鈥檚 compelling and thoughtful book The Ends of the World gives me an excellent starting point not least because they put forward their propositions with such admirable clarity.3 I appear in the section of the book in which they criticize my having resorted to the biological concept of 鈥渟pecies鈥 (as used by the recently departed E. O. Wilson) in the original version of my 2009 essay 鈥淭he Climate of History: Four Theses,鈥 now revised and reprinted as chapter 1 of The Climate of History in a Planetary Age.4 As they explain,
We must begin by rejecting any sole candidate to the (in)dignity of being the Anthropocene鈥檚 eponymous. The [E. O.] Wilsonian notion of species is dismissed less on the grounds of its phenomenological evanescence, as in Chakrabarty, than because it is a tributary of modernity鈥檚 apolitical, ahistorical conception of Nature, as well as of the Science鈥檚 absolute power of arbitrage. But neither are the revolutionary masses of the classical left, that other recurring incarnation of the modern universal, up to the task; . . . their liberation continues to depend on a generalization and intensification of the modernization front, on the practical (environmental destruction) as well as theoretical (the cult of Nature and Reason) levels.5
Their particular criticism of my essay is not important here. Instead I want to highlight two terms of their critique that are central to this discussion: 鈥渕odernity鈥檚 apolitical, ahistorical conception of Nature鈥 and 鈥淪cience鈥檚 absolute power of arbitrage.鈥 Danowski and de Castro go on to write:
The properly ethnopolitical situation of 鈥渉uman鈥 as intensive and extensive multiplicity of peoples must be acknowledged as being directly implicated in the Anthropocene crisis. If there is no positive human interest, it is because there is a diversity of political alignments among the various world peoples or 鈥渃ultures鈥 with several other non-human actants and peoples (constituting what Latour calls 鈥渃ollectives鈥) against the self-appointed spokespeople of the universal Human.6
This line of critique is in continuity with the intellectual program that de Castro had mapped out in his earlier collection of essays Cannibal Metaphysics.7 That program was to make anthropology into a 鈥減ermanent exercise in the decolonization of thought.鈥8 Based on his imaginative reading and analysis of what he called Amerindian 鈥減erspectivism鈥 and their 鈥渕ulti-naturalism,鈥 this decolonizing vision saw both humans and the world as 鈥渘on-unified,鈥 with all prospects of unification lying 鈥渋n the future, under what we would call a multiple hypothetical mode, and will depend on negotiating capacities once the 鈥榳ar of the worlds,鈥 as Latour has called it . . . has been declared.鈥9 As de Castro鈥檚 writings make clear and as he often explains, much of the inspiration for this particular mode of decolonizing thought came from the explosive impact that Deleuze and Guattari鈥檚 work on the figures of the 鈥渟avage,鈥 the 鈥減rimitive,鈥 the 鈥渞hizomatic,鈥 and the nomad had on French thought following the events of May 1968, when France was rocked by a revolutionary upheaval of working-class and student protesters, resulting in many weeks of violent civil unrest, economic and political uncertainty, and a profound questioning of orthodox Communists. 鈥淔or my generation,鈥 writes de Castro, 鈥渢he name of Gilles Deleuze immediately evokes the change in thought that marked the period circa 1968, when some key elements of our contemporary cultural apperception were invented. The meaning, consequences and the very reality of this change have given rise to a still-raging controversy.鈥10 He introduces his own book Cannibal Metaphysics as one that 鈥減uts forward and illustrates a theory of multiplicities鈥搕he Deleuzian theme that has carried the greatest repercussions in and for contemporary anthropology,鈥 influencing, among others, Latour鈥檚 critique of modernity in his We Have Never Been Modern.11 As de Castro further explicates, echoing the title of Latour鈥檚 book,
the concept of multiplicity may have only become thinkable鈥揳nd therefore thinkable by anthropology鈥揵ecause we are currently entering a nonmerologic, postpopular world where we have never been modern; a world that, more through disinterest than any Aufhebung, is leaving in the dust the old infernal distinction between the One and the Multiple that governed so many dualisms, the anthropological pairs and many others as well. . . . Thinking through multiplicities is thinking against the State.12
And then again: 鈥淢ultiplicity is not something like a larger unity, a superior plurality or unity; rather it is a less than one obtained by subtraction (hence the importance of the idea of the minor, minority, and minoritization in Deleuze).鈥13
Whether we look at de Castro and Danowski鈥檚 work or that of Deleuze and Guattari, the Indigenous remains the privileged site and the original instance of this subversive principle of multiplicity, often seen as embodying some kind of an Other to the statist ideas of history and modernization that imperial Europe epitomized.14 鈥淭hinking through multiplicities,鈥 writes de Castro, 鈥渋s thinking against the state.鈥15 In a significant footnote, de Castro mentions that he wrote this sentence in memory of Pierre Clastres, 鈥渨ho was (and remains) one of the rare French anthropologists who knew how to make something out of Anti-Oedipus鈥檚 ideas, besides being one of the inspirations for the theory of the war machine developed in Plateaus 12 and 13 of A Thousand Plateaus.鈥16 Indeed, one of the pivotal oppositions around which the text of Deleuze and Guattari鈥檚 Anti-Oedipus turned was that between the nomadic and the sedentary. In his preface that described the book as an 鈥渋ntroduction to the non-fascist life,鈥 Michel Foucault exhorted the reader to
withdraw allegiance from the old categories of the Negative (law, limit, castration, lack, lacuna), which Western thought has so long held sacred as a form of power and an access to reality. Prefer what is positive and multiple, difference over uniformity, flows over unities, mobile arrangements over systems.
And in all this the figure of the nomad that subsumed that of the 鈥渟avage鈥 or the 鈥減rimitive鈥 came to occupy a central position. Foucault鈥檚 injunction to the reader of Deleuze and Guattari was telling: 鈥淏elieve that what is productive is not sedentary but nomadic.鈥17
Deleuze and Guattari opened the famous third chapter of their Anti-Oedipus鈥 鈥淪avages, Barbarians, Civilized Men鈥濃揵y asking, 鈥渨here do we find enough innocence鈥 that would allow humans to generate 鈥渦niversal history鈥 after 鈥渢he universal鈥 had been brought to an end by 鈥渢he conditions determined by an apparently victorious capitalism?鈥18 鈥淚nnocence鈥 was not a matter of a dialectical reversal of a binary opposition, not in the way that the idea of a 鈥減rimitive communism鈥 would be preserved and sublimated into the Marxist ideal of communist society. For Deleuze and Guattari recognized that 鈥渦niversal history鈥 was always 鈥渢he history of contingencies, and not the history of necessity.鈥 The 鈥減rimitive system鈥 was self-sustaining, its 鈥渄eath . . . always comes from without: history is the history of contingencies and encounters.鈥19 The path back to universal history would similarly include 鈥渞uptures and limits,鈥 鈥済reat accidents . . . and amazing encounters that . . . might have never happened.鈥20 The 鈥減rimitive鈥 or the 鈥渟avage,鈥 however, supplied a principle critical to the generation of a universal human history, the potential for which capital had destroyed. And hence Deleuze and Guattari鈥檚 perennial interest in the ethnographic literature on segmentary, acephalic societies. The critical political principle was articulated by placing the nomadic in opposition to the State in their respective relationships to the Earth. 鈥淥nly the apparatus of the State will be territorial,鈥 write our authors, citing Engels, for 鈥渋t 鈥榮ubdivides not the people but the territory,鈥 and substitutes a geographic organization for the organization of gens.鈥 But 鈥渨here kinship seems to predominate over the earth, it is not difficult to show the importance of local ties.鈥 Deleuze and Guattari continue:
This is because the primitive machine subdivides the people, but does so on an indivisible earth where the connective, disjunctive, and conjunctive relations of each section are inscribed along with other relations (thus, for example, the coexistence or complementarity of the section chief and the guardian of the earth). When the division extends to the earth itself, by virtue of an administration that is landed and residential, this cannot be regarded as a promotion of territoriality; on the contrary, it is rather the effect of the first great movement of deterritorialization on the primitive communes. . . . Hence the savage, primitive was indeed the only territorial machine in the strict sense of the term. . . . before there is State.21
Ethnographic information about 鈥減rimitive, segmentary societies鈥 was eventually worked up into the science of nomadology, the twelfth chapter of A Thousand Plateaus, published in 1980 as the second volume of Anti-Oedipus. A part of this chapter鈥揚roposition II鈥搘as written in amicable disagreement with but also as 鈥渁 tribute to the memory鈥 of Pierre Clastres.22 The starting point once again was the observation that 鈥減rimitive, segmentary societies鈥 were not only 鈥渟ocieties without a State鈥; they were actively organized to keep the state at bay. In disagreement with Clastres, however, Deleuze and Guattari also claimed that such societies did not inhabit 鈥渁 state of nature鈥 that would enable them to remain untouched by the state. The sedentary and nomadic thus did not constitute a mutually exclusive binary.23 鈥淭he law of the State is not the law of All or Nothing (State-societies or counter-State societies) but that of interior and exterior.鈥24 There are 鈥渉uge worldwide machines鈥濃搇ike multinational corporations or religious organizations鈥搕hat 鈥渆njoy a large measure of autonomy in relation to States,鈥 and there are also 鈥渓ocal mechanisms of bands, margins, minorities, which continue to affirm the rights of segmentary societies in opposition to the organs of State power.鈥25 Together they constitute the exterior to the state but not a binary outside. And 鈥渓ocal mechanism鈥 of bands and minorities embodies and illustrates the principles of nomadology.
It is on this terrain of thought鈥揳nd especially the pacesetting work of Deleuze and Guattari in the wake of May 1968鈥搕hat the figure of the Indigenous presents itself on the pages of Latour鈥檚 We Have Never Been Modern and in Danowski and de Castro鈥檚 decolonizing exercise in The Ends of the World. Three parties are created in effect in this narrative of a global history of modernity and modernization. I will present them as they are depicted in Danowski and de Castro鈥檚 text, which is in deep conversation with Latour鈥檚 work, predominantly the latter鈥檚 two books, We Have Never Been Modern and Facing Gaia.26 These parties are鈥搃n order of their 鈥渋mportance鈥 and in my terminology鈥撯渢he original Moderns,鈥 鈥渢he Indigenous,鈥 and 鈥渢he later moderns.鈥 I am not sure where the enslaved of the North Atlantic would fall in this three-fold distinction, but some of their representatives will turn up in my discussion below. For now, let me stay with this three-fold division.
We know the theoretico-historical lineages of the Indigenous in this body of thought on the Europeanization of the Earth. They are designated 鈥渘on-Moderns.鈥 Who are the original-Moderns and why are they 鈥渙riginal鈥? The 鈥渙riginal-颅Moderns鈥 are North-Western Europeans, for they are the 鈥淗umans of the Holocene鈥 against whom the Terrans (the living who are opposed to the forces that cause global warming) are up in arms in the geostory that Latour presented in his Gifford Lectures published as Facing Gaia. As Danowski and de Castro gloss Latour鈥檚 text, 鈥淭hese are, it is well understood, none other than the Moderns, that race鈥originally North-Western, but increasingly less European and more Chinese, Indian, Brazilian.鈥27 The 鈥淥riginal-Moderns鈥 are 鈥渙riginal鈥 in two senses. They are the first to become 鈥渕odern鈥; it is only later that they discover that, 鈥渋n the East and in the South, other people had learned their lesson too well, taking upon themselves the will and the responsibility for modernization, but in their own, frightful terms.鈥28 Thus, as modernizers in the East and the South, the Chinese, [the Japanese], the Indians, the Brazilian, and others become un-original in two senses: they are un-original in that they come later with the Europeans as their predecessors, but they are also un-original in that they are 鈥渄erivatives,鈥 pale copies, as indeed the etymology of the word 鈥渙riginal鈥濃揻rom Latin origo meaning source, birth鈥搒uggests.
Danowski and de Castro are aware of the contemporary demographic weight of the unoriginal-Moderns compared to numbers of the non-Moderns. The 370 million Indigenous people 鈥渟pread over 70 countries in the world, according to a recent United Nations Permanent Forum of Indigenous Issues (2009) estimate,鈥 are 鈥渃ertainly nowhere near the roughly 3.5 billion (read half the human species) crowding our 鈥榯echnical metropolises,鈥 around a billion of which, it should be noted, live in not particularly 鈥榯echnical鈥 slums.鈥29 Yet in spite of their demographic minority鈥搊r because of it鈥搕he 鈥渘on-Moderns鈥 will carry in Danowski and de Castro鈥檚 account a moral weight far out of proportion to their numbers. The reason is simple. The Moderns, original or late, represent a failed project that has now resulted in a catastrophe:
Assured of their privileged access to Nature, Moderns saw themselves as a civilizing force come to convince recalcitrant people to rally to the flag of a common world (a single ontological and cosmopolitical regime) that was also, not by coincidence, the world of the Moderns.30
The scientific facts are not at issue, for 鈥渨e are not discussing if there are such things as global warming and an ongoing environmental collapse; these are among the best-documented . . . phenomena in the history of sciences. . . . [T]here is hardly any significant controversy among scientists concerning the anthropic origin of climate catastrophe.鈥31 The dissemination of this knowledge may even be an 鈥渋mportant factor鈥 in bringing people over to the side of the good. But the project of the Moderns cannot unite humanity anymore. 鈥淎ll unification lies in the future,鈥 in a postcatastrophic world.32 The forces for the good 鈥渃annot but be an 鈥榠rremediably minor鈥 people鈥 (minor in a Deleuzian sense), resembling
less the 鈥減hantom public鈥 of Western democracies than the people that is missing which Deleuze and Guattari speak of: Kafka and Melville鈥檚 minor people, Rimbaud鈥檚 inferior races, the Indian that the philosopher becomes . . . 鈥 the people, that is, to come; capable of launching a 鈥渞esistance to the present鈥 and thus of creating a 鈥渘ew earth,鈥 the world to come.33
It is in 鈥渁 post-catastrophic time, or, if one wishes, in a permanently diminished human world鈥 that 鈥渢he generally small populations and 鈥榬elatively weak鈥 technologies of indigenous peoples and so many other sociopolitical minorities of the Earth could become a crucial advantage and resource.鈥34
Now, the question is not whether Indigenous peoples鈥 thoughts and practices could provide both intellectual and practical resources as humans search for a way out of their planetary environmental crises. They, of course, do, and Danowski and de Castro鈥檚 work (here and elsewhere) shows us how. But it is interesting to observe that their method of effecting a 鈥減ermanent decolonization鈥 of anthropological thought鈥搈uch like the Deleuzian tradition from which they take inspiration鈥揹oes not connect with the emancipatory dreams not only of the late and revolutionary modernizers of Japan, China, India, and Africa, but also of someone like Franz Fanon or, for that matter, B. R. Ambedkar, the greatest modern leader of the Dalits in India, who once publicly asked for Indian society to be completely rebuilt on the principles of liberty, equality, and fraternity!35 Instead, these late-Modernizers, considered 鈥渦noriginal鈥 and 鈥渄erivative,鈥 are folded back into the story of the 鈥渙riginal鈥 European-Moderns. But this is ignoring鈥搕o continue to speak with Deleuze and Guattari鈥搕he ruptures, discontinuities, and contingencies that made modernity what it was in Asia, Africa, and Latin America, where lives were impacted by the domination and racism of European powers but without, as in the case of India, any active elaboration of the near-genocidal logic of European settler-colonial rule.36 Without that history of Asia (and parts of Africa and Latin America), as we have seen, human history would not have undergone the Great Acceleration or acquired its complexity, what Foucault, always more of a historian than Deleuze and Guattari, called 鈥渙ur immediate and concrete actuality.鈥37
Imagine how the present could have been different if the human population had stabilized in the 1950s or if the world had sourced its energy requirements from nuclear power. Many of our current problems would have still been there and the problem of disposing of radioactive waste would have been much more intense, but the warming would have been less. There is no politics of the planetary predicament of humans without dealing with issues of climate justice that have to do, profoundly, with the emancipatory aspirations and expectation, and not just fossilized carbon, that still fuel the desire for 鈥済rowth and development鈥 in the new, populous nations that have now experienced for decades the phenomenon of 鈥渕ass poverty.鈥 There is nothing morally wrong, as such, with humans wanting to live better and longer, so long as they did not imperil themselves. Besides, while I agree with Latour, de Castro, and others that the consumerist model of capitalist development is unsustainable for most humans, nothing guarantees de Castro鈥檚 hope: that a climate disaster resulting in 鈥減ermanently diminished鈥 human capabilities will give humanity yet another chance at flourishing by making the right use of the accumulated wisdom of the Indigenous non-Moderns. That may or may not come to pass.
Bruno Latour and historian Christophe Bonneuil have helpfully reminded us that there are many ideas about planetarity that circulate at any given time.38 This was as true of the past and as it is of the present. From the prehistoric humans who settled the Pacific Islands thousands of years ago navigating the seas by the night sky to ancient Greek and Indian astrology to peasants鈥 sayings about seasons, through to the Copernican revolution in the sciences and its consequences: these are all instances of planetary thinking. Bonneuil, borrowing from Hartog鈥檚 expression 鈥渞egimes of historicity,鈥 makes the additional useful suggestion that while there have been different traditions of planetary thinking, there have also been dominant regimes of planetarity鈥損lanetary ideas that enjoyed the backing of powers that be in any society.39
One could similarly argue that the 鈥淓arth system鈥 that Earth system science speaks of鈥揳 planet for which geological and biological processes and histories cannot be thought in complete separation from one another鈥搃s a particular way of conceiving of the planet we live on, while there may very well be other competing ways of thinking about the planet (as both Latour and Bonneuil show), ancient, Modern, and non-Modern. I would also happily concede the point that Earth system science, given the role it has played in both positing and explaining the anthropogenic origins of the current episode of planetary warming that the Earth is undergoing, represents a dominant regime of planetarity, given the big-ticket funding that has made this science possible, and the backing it has received from the powerful nations of the world, the United Nations, and various other international organizations. This is also what gives this science a touch of irony. It is a product of the Cold War and is dependent on the technological advances that conflict produced. As Paul Crutzen, the pioneer of the Anthropocene idea in our generation, once said, putting a positive spin on the irony:
Our negative impacts help us to understand the world. My research on our atmosphere has really terrified me. But finally I thought: What would we have known about the atmosphere if it had not been polluted? Because pollution gave us the impetus and triggered the funding to study the workings of the environment.40
I would also submit, against those who seem to conflate 鈥渟cientific knowledge鈥 with the power structures within which scientific research is embedded, that while power structures may very well determine what kinds of knowledge the sciences will produce鈥揳 poorly funded climate science may indeed look different (whence follow the politics of funding)鈥搕he knowledge produced still must go through the acceptable procedures and protocols of such production. Every consensus in the sciences exists only to be challenged by new research, which is why consensuses are much harder won than in the humanities, which in contrast and by its very nature often appears to be a collection of schismatic churches and their conflicting dogma.
What distinguishes 鈥渢he regime of planetarity鈥 that Earth system science represents is what the singular word system suggests. It refers to the way that geology and biology have come to combine in the history of this planet to act like a system supporting the existence of life鈥揷omplex, multicellular life鈥搊n Earth, making it the only 鈥淕oldilocks planet鈥 we so far know.41 This system is not something we can directly perceive or experience even through a telescope; the word system here refers to an implicitly heuristic model built on the basis of both observed data and computer modeling, something that seeks to approximate how the Earth system works. Unlike in the case of Indigenous or peasant ideas of planetarity, the idea of the Earth system refers to the roles that parts of the planet that humans have never experienced鈥搕he deep seas, for instance, or the ozone layer or the carbon cycles of the planet鈥損lay in maintaining its climate system, a system thought of as planetary in scope. Unlike in many other traditions of planetary thinking, Earth system science speaks of time and space on scales that go far beyond what humans can phenomenologically experience. It is for this reason that, read through the findings and propositions of Earth system science, the climate crisis becomes a human encounter with the idea of ourselves as a geological force, an encounter, that is, both with geological deep time and with our entanglement with other forms of life and thus with the geobiological history of the planet. Humanists are still working out the implications of this encounter.
The problem of the 鈥渨e鈥 is, in fact, the most critical human aspect of our current planetary crisis. There is no one we to respond to a planet that is studied by climate scientists as one. If the evidence of human history is anything to go by, there never has been a one we of humans. Yet a fallacious aspect of much rational thinking in the humanities is signaled by the constant invoking of a potential we of humans as part of conditional solution-proposing statements that take the form of 鈥淚f only we . . . .鈥 Steven Pinker, the well-known devotee of the European Enlightenment and its legacies, is a good case in point. Here is how he explains his 鈥渃onditional optimism,鈥 faced with the facts of anthropogenic climate change:
Despite a half-century of panic, humanity is not on an irrevocable path to ecological suicide. The fear of resource shortage is misconceived. So is the misanthropic environmentalism that sees modern humans as vile despoilers of a pristine planet. . . . Problems are solvable. That does not mean they will solve themselves, but it does mean that we can solve them if we sustain the benevolent forces of modernity that have allowed us to solve problems so far, including societal prosperity, wisely regulated markets, international governance, and investments in science and technology.42
Pinker鈥檚 conditional optimism leads him to support physicist David Keith鈥檚 projects for 鈥渕oderate, responsive, and temporary鈥 climate engineering designed 鈥渙nly to give humanity breathing space until it eliminates greenhouse gas emissions and brings the CO2 in the atmosphere back to preindustrial levels.鈥43 But there is no agreement among even those who study the phenomenon of geo颅engineering that it will be an unmixed good for humanity. There is, for instance, philosopher Fr茅d茅ric Neyrat鈥檚 considered, humanist, and thoughtful critique of geoengineering that argues for humans acquiring 鈥渁 capacity for stepping back and regaining some distance [from what they have an impact on]鈥 in a gesture that does not assume a seamless continuity between humans and their 鈥渆nvironment.鈥 But will Neyrat鈥檚 argument find any more consensus than Pinker鈥檚? One can safely say, 鈥渘o.鈥 Yet the question of 鈥渨hat is to be done?鈥 will resonate through human thought even as humans remain decisively not-one. This mismatch between the oneness of the planet (IPCC鈥檚 assumption) and the not-one-ness of humans will keep open the place for decolonial and postcolonial political thought jostling together and around the intensifying problems of anthropogenic climate change.