亚色影库app

An open access publication of the 亚色影库app & Sciences
Spring 2009

Pragmatism & the lessons of experience

Author
John Kaag

John Jacob Kaag, a Visiting Scholar at the Academy in 2007鈥2008, is an assistant professor of philosophy at the University of Massachusetts, Lowell. His publications include 鈥淐hance and Creativity: The Nature of Contingency in Classical American Philosophy鈥 (Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, vol. 44, no. 3, Summer 2008) and 鈥淎merican Interpretations of Hegel: Josiah Royce's Philosophy of Loyalty鈥 (History of Philosophy Quarterly, vol. 26, no. 1, 2009).

Experience has lessons to impart. Its ability to teach, however, turns on our willingness to learn. Attending to the lessons of human experience brought American pragmatists of the nineteenth century to a new conception of philosophy, one that embraced the fallibilism that had long defined the natural sciences. It led them back to the abiding existential questions that underpinned the Wisdom Traditions of the past in order to explore the personal, social, and political trials of the present. These thinkers established a new intellectual tradition that allows us to 鈥渓earn from experience.鈥1

Classical pragmatism stood against the prevailing current of European philosophy, which continued to be motivated by Immanuel Kant鈥檚 insistence that philosophy should be concerned with the limits and conditions of 鈥減ure reason,鈥 that is, reason devoid of empirical content. In contrast, American intellectuals such as Charles Sanders Peirce, William James, Jane Addams, Ella Lyman Cabot, and John Dewey held that philosophy should concern itself with the messiness of human meaning, which James acknowledged as 鈥渧arious, tangled and painful.鈥 Philosophy ought to be understood, they thought, as the result of human beings thinking through the meaningful questions of living as embodied, thoughtful organisms. These questions can never be purely cerebral; they are laden with emotion, carefully negotiated in daily life, and pressed upon us in moments of personal and social crisis鈥揳lways, therefore, empirically conditioned and experiential. Experience was to replace pure reason as American pragmatism鈥檚 enduring lodestone.

Pragmatism took the reconstruction of experience as its principal task: the only way to respond effectively to the dilemma that philosophy faced in the early years of the twentieth century. In 1907, William James called it the 鈥減resent dilemma,鈥 but it now is more accurate to call it a perennial one. It is the crisis that philosophy faces when it jeopardizes its own relevance. Academic philosophy has spent the better part of the past century earning a deservedly bad reputation. Since the time of Socrates and Aristophanes, philosophy has been accused of being only loosely tethered to the world of human affairs, and today the string appears to have been severed completely. As Dewey noted in 1917, the 鈥渞ecovery of philosophy鈥 is only possible if philosophers are willing to take a stand with the sciences, and a variety of other academic disciplines, on the ground of human experience.

.  .  .

To read this essay or subscribe to 顿忙诲补濒耻蝉, visit the 顿忙诲补濒耻蝉 access page
Access now

Endnotes

  • 11 I would like to thank Dr. Robert Innis for his suggestions and encouragement in the drafting of this article.