亚色影库app

An open access publication of the 亚色影库app & Sciences
Fall 2008

Threats to judicial independence, real & imagined

Author
Viet D. Dinh
View PDF

Viet D. Dinh is professor of law and codirector of the Asian Law and Policy Studies Program at Georgetown University Law Center.

Public criticism of the federal courts is nothing new.1 Since the beginning of the republic to the present day, politicians and populace have attacked judicial opinions and decried judicial activism. For example, the response to the landmark Supreme Court decisions of the 1950s, in particular those involving desegregation and church-state relations, was a nationwide movement to remove Chief Justice Warren from the bench.2 Billboards around the country proclaimed their aim: 鈥淚mpeach Earl Warren.鈥3 Petitions circulated, and over one million Americans signed their names in support of the impeachment effort.4 Some even proposed that Warren be hanged.

For as long as there has been a federal judiciary, federal judges have been blasted for purportedly overstepping their bounds. Yet by and large the judges have not abdicated their duty to invalidate laws that they believe offend the Constitution. Public criticism of judicial decisions does not, by itself, necessarily threaten the independence of the judiciary; in fact, under some circumstances, such critiques paradoxically can help bring about a more robust form of judicial independence.

Under our constitutional system, the federal judiciary wields carefully circumscribed powers, but within its proper sphere judicial authority is final and therefore absolute. Among other limitations, federal judges may not issue advisory opinions and have no authority to engage in policy-making. But while the Constitution rules certain functions out of bounds for the courts, it also insulates federal judges from the pressures that can be brought to bear in response to an unpopular, but legally required, decision. Article III guarantees that federal judges shall hold their offices for life with continued 鈥済ood Behaviour.鈥 By setting up an independent judiciary, the framers intended to prevent the other branches of government, or the people themselves, from undermining the judiciary鈥檚 decisional impartiality. It is 鈥渆ssential to the preservation of the rights of every individual, his life, property, and character, that there be an impartial interpretation of the laws, and administration of justice.鈥5 The insulation of judges from popular pressures ensures that all citizens receive equal justice under the law, and prevents judges from being influenced by the whims of the public (or a powerful faction) when they decide cases. In The Federalist No. 78, Alexander Hamilton emphasized:

This independence of the judges is equally requisite to guard the Constitution and the rights of individuals from the effects of those ill humors, which the arts of designing men, or the influence of particular conjectures, sometimes disseminate among the people themselves, and which, though they speedily give place to better information and more deliberate reflection, have a tendency, in the meantime, to occasion dangerous innovations in the government, and serious oppressions of the minor party in the community.

The way to achieve this impartiality 鈥 to free judges to decide cases based on what the law actually requires, and on nothing else 鈥 is to ensure that the judiciary is independent, or, put differently, not subject to reprisals for decisions on the bench.

But judicial independence is not an absolute or singular value defining our courts. The principle of judicial restraint is equally important 鈥 and it is inextricably linked to judicial independence. At one level, the tension between the two seems inescapable. But there is an important sense in which an independent judiciary and judicial restraint are flip sides of the same coin. Both aim to minimize the influence of extraneous factors on judicial decision-making. A judge must not decide a case with an eye toward public approbation, because whether a particular result is popular is irrelevant to whether it is legally sound. In the same way, a judge must not consult his own policy preferences (or those of whatever moral philosopher happens to be au courant at the time) when construing the Constitution or a statute, because those personal views are immaterial to what the law, fairly construed, actually provides. Judicial independence and judicial restraint thus work together hand-in-glove to channel judges鈥 attention to the factors that are actually relevant to the proper resolution of cases.

Much is at stake if the judiciary becomes too independent or too restrained, namely individual rights and the proper functioning of the government. Those who criticize courts advocate more restraint to ensure that judges do not exceed the scope of their powers. But at the same time, it must be stressed, as Justice Sandra Day O鈥機onnor did in a recent speech, that a court鈥檚 ability to be effective depends 鈥渙n the notion that we won鈥檛 be subject to retaliation for our judicial acts.鈥6 The upside of judicial independence, then, is that it insulates judges who faithfully apply the law (albeit in unpopular ways); the downside is that judicial independence insulates judges who use their lack of accountability to shape the law in favor of their own preferred policies.

Criticism of courts comes in many forms, and recent years have witnessed many if not all of the variations. But if we compare the nature and intensity of today鈥檚 criticisms with the vitriol directed at judges in years past, it becomes apparent that they are not unique. Indeed, public critiques of federal judges have been commonplace throughout American history and, when done thoughtfully and honestly, they contribute both to a healthy democracy and to judicial independence.7

Congress has attempted to enact legislation that restricts or eliminates the jurisdiction of federal courts to hear certain types of cases. Congress鈥檚 power to do so derives from the Exceptions Clause,8 which provides that 鈥渢he supreme Court shall have appellate Jurisdiction, both as to Law and Fact, with such Exceptions, and under such Regulations as the Congress shall make.鈥 The best-known of these limitations concerns review by federal courts of prior adjudications by other bodies, such as administrative agencies or state courts. In the early 1990s, the public (and some members of Congress) grew increasingly frustrated with what was perceived as federal courts鈥 penchant for allowing state convicts to relitigate their cases in the federal system. In response to these and other concerns (including fears about terrorism), Congress in 1996 enacted the Anti-Terrorism and Effective Death Penalty Act (AEDPA).9 Among other things, AEDPA limits the ability of federal courts to consider habeas challenges to state-court criminal convictions.

Similar concerns led Congress (also in 1996) to enact the Illegal Immigration Reform and Immigrant Responsibility Act (IIRIRA).10 The IIRIRA prevents federal courts from reviewing a final order of the Immigration and Naturalization Service to deport a person with a criminal record, and expands the class of crimes that constitute an aggravated felony, including terrorism. More recently, in December 2005, just months before the Supreme Court was scheduled to hear the Hamdan v. Rumsfeld case, Congress passed and the president signed the Detainee Treatment Act (DTA),11 which purported to remove from the federal courts jurisdiction to hear challenges brought by suspected terrorists to their detention and treatment at Guant谩namo Bay. After the Supreme Court held in Hamdan that the DTA did not strip the courts of jurisdiction over habeas petitions pending during the DTA鈥檚 enactment, Congress and the president tried again. They passed the Military Commissions Act of 2006, which stripped federal courts of jurisdiction over Guant谩namo detainees鈥 cases, including those that were pending.

The 109th Congress was asked to remove federal court jurisdiction to review the constitutionality of hot-button issues, like abortion. The Marriage Protection Act of 2005 intended to strip federal courts of jurisdiction to consider the constitutionality of the Defense of Marriage Act, which declares that no state shall be required to recognize legally same-sex marriages performed in another state.12 Other proposals aimed to deny courts jurisdiction to assess the constitutionality of the Pledge of Allegiance13 and public displays of the Ten Commandments.14 While all of these measures failed to secure final passage by Congress, they have been reintroduced in the 110th Congress.15

Jurisdiction-stripping is not a new phenomenon. Congress has exercised the authority to strip federal courts of jurisdiction for centuries, and judicial independence has not suffered measurably for it. The Supreme Court鈥檚 decision in Ex parte McCardle affirmed the power of Congress to restrict the jurisdiction of the Article III courts, upholding a law that removed from the Court鈥檚 jurisdiction any cases appealed from circuit courts under the Act of 1867.16 In fact, like the Detainee Treatment Act, which was passed while Hamdan was pending, the law at issue in McCardle was enacted while the McCardle case was pending before the Supreme Court. And the judiciary responds when it deems necessary. For example, in the recent Boumediene v. Bush decision, the Supreme Court held that Congress unconstitutionally suspended the writ of habeas corpus by stripping the federal courts of jurisdiction to hear habeas actions of Guant谩namo detainees.

Criticism of judges by politicians is not new either, but its frequency has picked up in recent decades. While virtually everyone agrees that federal judges may be impeached if they commit crimes,17 in the modern era threats of impeachment often follow unpopular rulings. In 1996, Judge Harold Baer, a federal district judge in New York, ordered the suppression of evidence found during a traffic stop in New York City鈥檚 Washington Heights neighborhood. The judge reckoned that, in that neighborhood, it was understandable for people to fear the police, and so the defendants鈥 running did not give the officers a reasonable basis for searching the car.18 Judge Baer鈥檚 ruling was immediately denounced, by members of both political parties. The Clinton administration called for the judge鈥檚 resignation, while some congressional Republicans proposed impeachment. Several weeks later, Judge Baer reconsidered the case and reversed his prior ruling.19 His critics were victorious.

More recently, former House Majority Leader Tom DeLay advocated impeachment investigations of several sitting judges such that Congress could be 鈥渁 check on the court system.鈥20 The House Judiciary Committee has considered creating an office of inspector general for the judiciary, to investigate allegations of judicial misconduct. The goal of such proceedings is not necessarily to remove the judges from the bench. Rather, threats of impeachment can serve as a tool of intimidation, having a chilling effect that encourages judges to look over their shoulders when deciding cases.

While the volume of criticisms may be louder now than in the past, the fact is that federal judges have endured threats of impeachment for years. Perhaps the most famous example dates from the earliest days of the republic. In 1805, President Thomas Jefferson, a Democratic-Republican, supported an effort to impeach Justice Samuel Chase because he objected to Chase鈥檚 Federalist jurisprudence.21 The script will be familiar to any observer of today鈥檚 debates over the conduct of the courts: Jefferson attacked Chase for what he characterized as judicial rulings that went beyond what was required law; for his part, Chase saw the attacks as an attempt to undermine judicial independence. In the early twentieth century, President Theodore Roosevelt often criticized rulings of the federal judiciary that blocked his preferred social reform legislation.22 Roosevelt鈥檚 platform as a Progressive Party candidate in 1912 advocated the recall of unpopular judicial opinions and judges by popular vote. And, of course, some who objected to the Warren Court鈥檚 rulings launched an advertising campaign, of which the most conspicuous feature was the 鈥淚mpeach Earl Warren鈥 billboards, in an effort to influence the Supreme Court justices. Federal judges have endured these criticisms with scant negative consequences for their independence, and there is no reason to suppose that today鈥檚 threats will prove any more effective.

The Senate has always closely examined nominees to the federal bench, but recently even closer attention has been paid to prospective judges鈥 ideological leanings. Historically, the Senate鈥檚 scrutiny has not been strictly limited to nominees鈥 professional qualifications, but also sometimes has included some inquiry into their general judicial philosophies. For years, the approach was to wave nominees through without much, if any, ideological examination. Until the 1930s, presidential judicial nominees were not even invited to testify before the Senate Judiciary Committee, and it was not until 1955 that testimony before the Senate was compelled.23 Prior to that point, nominees were not questioned about their positions on substantive legal issues. Still, for much of the latter half of the twentieth century, candidate questioning was mostly ceremonial, unless a particular nominee was controversial. Even as recently as Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg鈥檚 hearings, the nomination process was generally quiet; Ginsburg received careful scrutiny, but was not subjected to overly intrusive questioning. Indeed, at one point, Senator Strom Thurmond, who did not hail from the nominating president鈥檚 political party, even encouraged Ginsburg to decline to answer any questions she believed could come before her on the Court: 鈥淲ell, you don鈥檛 have to answer it, then, if you feel that you shouldn鈥檛.鈥24

Recent years have seen the Senate demand much more from judicial nominees; the Senate sometimes seeks assurances (implied, if not explicit) as to how nominees would rule in particular cases. Usually this takes the form of questions about the nominee鈥檚 personal views on controversial issues of the day: abortion, affirmative action, the death penalty, the rights of criminal defendants, and other topics. This growing trend dates at least from the Robert Bork and Clarence Thomas hearings. Robert Bork was questioned regarding how his judicial philosophy would affect his interpretation of key issues such as right to privacy, civil rights, gender discrimination, criminal procedure, separation of powers, antitrust law, and labor relations. He also fielded questions about his personal views on such controversial Supreme Court decisions as Griswold v. Connecticut, Roe v. Wade, and Brandenburg v. Ohio.

This growing trend also was evident at the recent Roberts and Alito hearings. During Chief Justice John Roberts鈥檚 confirmation hearings, one senator asserted that Roberts鈥檚 lack of a paper trail as a judge required him to divulge his views on critical issues. But when Justice Samuel Alito came before the Senate Judiciary Committee, the same senator argued that Alito鈥檚 sixteen-year record as a judge, and his correspondingly lengthy paper trail, necessitated that he be even more responsive than Roberts was.25 When Roberts and Alito declined to tell how they would rule on particular issues, the senator accused them of dodging. Another member of the Senate Judiciary Committee asked Alito鈥檚 opinion on Bush v. Gore, characterized as a 鈥済reat example of judicial activism.鈥26 Both justices were questioned at length on Roe v. Wade. Nor is such pointed questioning limited to nominees to the highest court. Probing questions also are asked increasingly of appellate nominees.27 Nominees are required to respond to a variety of inquiries ranging from their opinions on previous court decisions to whether they would adhere to particular precedents. Nominees also are asked their personal opinions on hot social and political issues and are queried about their opinions on issues they might need to adjudicate in the future.

This increased ideological scrutiny of nominees is problematic from the standpoint of both judicial independence and judicial restraint. It certainly is proper for senators to inquire about nominees鈥 general judicial philosophies and interpretive methodologies. But asking about a nominee鈥檚 preferred outcomes in particular cases 鈥 or trying to glean them from the nominee鈥檚 views on prior precedents 鈥 may pose a threat to the proper functioning of the federal judiciary. The danger is that judges will come to be agents of the Senate鈥檚 policy preferences, and that is no more acceptable than that judges should become the agents of the president鈥檚 policy preferences. 鈥淏y demanding to know in advance how a particular nominee will rule in a given kind of case, the political branches are exerting precisely the sort of direct control over the judiciary that Hamilton and the other Framers sought to avoid with the creation of a separate and distinct third branch.鈥28

The Supreme Court seldom finds itself in unanimity on controversial legal questions, but all nine members of the Court agree about the dangers of judges precommitting themselves to particular outcomes. In the 2002 case of Republican Party of Minnesota v. White, the Court struck down Minnesota鈥檚 Announce Clause, which prohibited candidates for elected judicial office from publicizing their views on disputed legal or political issues.29 The dissent acknowledged: 鈥淚n the context of the federal system, how a prospective nominee for the bench would resolve particular contentious issues would certainly be 鈥榦f interest鈥 to the President and the Senate. . . . But in accord with a longstanding norm, every Member of this Court declined to furnish such information to the Senate, and presumably to the President as well.鈥 That 鈥渓ongstanding norm鈥 was 鈥渃rucial to the health of the Federal Judiciary.鈥30 The majority did not dispute this, and only held that judges who wish to share their legal views cannot be forbidden from doing so: 鈥淣or do we assert that candidates for judicial office should be compelled to announce their views on disputed legal issues.鈥31

Recently the federal judiciary has been met with mounting criticism and a public that is increasingly skeptical of courts鈥 ability 鈥 even their willingness 鈥 to do their job properly. Critics worry that the judiciary, the least accountable branch, is abusing its authority and exercising undue influence over the nation鈥檚 political policy. In particular, critics see abuses of courts鈥 authority in what is loosely known as 鈥渏udicial activism鈥 and 鈥渃areer judging.鈥 Calling the judiciary to task for these practices is not only not a threat to the courts鈥 independence, it can be an important part of a robust democracy. Equally important, it can be a crucial part of safeguarding judicial independence: criticism can help ensure that judges perform only that role which has been delegated to them and consider law, not public opinion, when deciding cases.

The perennial criticism of judges is that they engage in judicial activism. Everyone seems opposed to judicial activism, yet no one agrees what it means. Some have branded as activist the Supreme Court鈥檚 recent rulings on partial-birth abortion, homosexual sodomy, and the death penalty.32 The Rehnquist Court was dubbed the most activist in history by some because of the number of federal statutes it struck down 鈥 more than three dozen federal laws.33 And it was not just for its rulings that the Rehnquist Court was deemed activist, but for the manner in which it went about undertaking judicial review, namely its perceived reluctance to show some deference to the constitutional interpretations of Congress and the president before striking down democratically passed legislation.

Some elements are common to many understandings of judicial activism. It can involve (1) deciding a case on the basis of one鈥檚 own policy preferences; (2) deciding a case on the basis of an en vogue philosophical theory;34 (3) reaching out to decide an issue the resolution of which is not essential to the outcome of the case;35 and (4) too readily discarding a prior precedent without considering whether it is entitled to stare decisis treatment.

This is not the place to define judicial activism with precision. Instead, my objective is to explain how judicial activism, however defined, and the public鈥檚 response to it relate to judicial independence. As mentioned above, judicial independence and judicial restraint (the opposite of activism) are inextricably tied to one another. Both aim to prevent judges from consulting extrinsic materials (whether public opinion or their personal views) when they decide cases. Seen in this light, public criticism of judges for activism is not necessarily a threat to judicial independence; it is a complement to judicial independence. After all, it remains the role of the legislature to legislate and the judiciary to interpret. An activist court 鈥渓egislates from the bench,鈥 and thus 鈥渆ncroaches on the legislature鈥檚 constitutional turf.鈥36 Legislating from the bench 鈥渄estroys the proper end of judging and, therefore, is the greatest threat to judicial independence, the means to that proper end.鈥37 Criticizing judges for judicial activism is a way of reminding judges to perform their proper function 鈥 interpreting the Constitution鈥揳s members of the judicial branch. Criticism encourages judges to realize more fully the practice of ignoring irrelevancies when they decide cases, the same objective that judicial independence strives to achieve.

Up to this point, I have voiced some doubts that public criticism of judges poses a severe threat to judicial independence. But there is one way in which pervasive criticism of judges鈥 decisions can compromise the independence of the courts, without offsetting benefits in the form of democratic participation or judicial restraint. A real danger exists that the publicly stated views of political elites 鈥 activists, the news media, and officeholders 鈥 will condition the environment in which judges operate, leading career-minded members of the federal judiciary to tailor their rulings to conform to the views of the politically influential.

The process by which career judges 鈥 those who seek promotion to higher or more prestigious courts 鈥 can internalize elite opinion is fairly straightforward. It is only natural that many state-court judges and judges on lower federal courts would seek to advance through the ranks. They know that presidents and senators historically have preferred to appoint judges who have previous judicial experience.38 They also know that judges whose prior rulings have proved unpalatable to presidents or senators have had a harder time being nominated and confirmed to new judicial posts. Such career judges thus will have an incentive to placate the officeholders who they anticipate would play a role in their future elevation (as well as the private opinion-makers who would hold forth on their nominations). Career judges will have reason to decide cases based not just on their honest estimation of what the law actually requires, but also, at the margins, on their sense of what outcomes the political elites may favor.

My sense is that the threat here largely comes from members of the elite: the presidents who nominate judges, the senators who decide whether to confirm them, the journalists and editorialists who cover the process, and the activists who bring pressure to bear on their allies in office. The threat to judicial independence does not come from criticisms leveled by ordinary members of the public (except insofar as those citizens have the power, either individually or collectively, to move elites). Judicial independence has more to fear from an editorial in The Washington Post than from a posting by an anonymous blogger.

A few qualifications are in order. This analysis is not meant to malign the integrity of American judges, who in my experience strive mightily to resolve legal disputes in good faith and seek to minimize the influence of external considerations when they decide cases. It is only to recognize that judges are human beings and that, as humans, they are susceptible to self-interest as everyone else. Note also that elite criticism sometimes can have the opposite effect. It can cause judges to dig in their heels and refuse to buckle in the face of public sentiment. The need to maintain judicial independence notwithstanding the views of powerful elements of the public was one of the reasons the Supreme Court in Planned Parenthood v. Casey cited as a basis for retaining Roe v. Wade.

How, then, do we counter (or at least minimize) the natural incentive to curry favor with elites that is experienced by judges who hope for elevation to a higher court? A good starting point would be to lower the temperature of the judicial-appointments process. Judges who have no reason to fear that the president or Senate will scrutinize their rulings, line by line, in a hunt for evidence of ideological orthodoxy (or heresy), will be less prone to craft those rulings to be amenable to elite opinion. This is not a call for the Senate to abdicate its historically robust and important role in the confirmation process. It is only a call to focus on nominees鈥 general judicial philosophies and interpretive methodologies in lieu of their preferred outcomes in particular cases.

Few would dispute that judges must be 鈥渇ree to make decisions according to the law, without regard to political or public pressure.鈥39 But judicial independence is not a one-way street. We insulate our judges from day-to-day public pressures not because we want them to function as platonic guardians of the public interest, but precisely because in our constitutional system their role is so carefully circumscribed. In other words, the principal beneficiaries of judicial independence are not the judges themselves, but the litigants who appear before them in the hopes of getting a fair shake, and, ultimately, the American people who look to their courts for impartiality. Seen in this light, public criticism of the courts does not invariably present a threat to judicial independence, but actually can play a key role in ensuring that the judiciary remains independent. Such critiques are a way of calling on judges to remain faithful to their role as detached expounders of the law, and to eschew irrelevancies such as their own predilections and public opinion when deciding cases. As Chief Justice William Howard Taft cautioned, 鈥淣othing tends more to render judges careful in their decisions and anxiously solicitous to do exact justice than the consciousness that every act of theirs is to be subject to the intelligent scrutiny of their fellow men, and to their candid criticism.鈥40

ENDNOTES

1 A modified version of this essay first appeared in The Georgetown Law Journal 95 (4) (2007).

2 Kelly A. MacGrady and John W. Van Doren, 鈥淎ALS Constitutional Law Panel on Brown, Another Council of Nicaea?鈥 Akron Law Review 35 (2002): 373, which cites Ed Cray, Chief Justice: A Biography of Earl Warren (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1997), 389鈥392.

3 See Charles J. Ogletree, Jr., 鈥淛udicial Activism or Judicial Necessity: The D.C. District Court鈥檚 Criminal Justice Legacy,鈥 The Georgetown Law Journal; 90 (2002): 693, which cites Kermit L. Hall, 鈥淭he Warren Court: Yesterday, Today, and Tomorrow,鈥 Indiana Law Review 28 (1995): 326.

4 Robert L. Brown, 鈥淔rom Earl Warren to Wendell Griffen: A Study of Judicial Intimidation and Judicial Self-Restraint,鈥 University of Arkansas at Little Rock Law Review 28 (2005): 2鈥3.

5 Peter D. Webster, 鈥淲ho Needs an Independent Judiciary?鈥 Florida Bar Journal 78 (2004): 24鈥25, which discusses the creation of and need for an independent judiciary.

6 Editorial, 鈥淚njudicious Intimidation,鈥 Detroit Free Press, April 16, 2006.

7 Melvin B. Lewis, 鈥淐riticism of Court Challenged,鈥 Chicago Tribune, October 16, 1985.

8 U.S. Const., article III, section 2.

9 Public Law No. 104鈥132 (1996).

10 Public Law No. 104鈥208 (1996).

11 Public Law No. 109鈥148, sections 1001鈥1006 (2005).

12 Marriage Protection Act of 2005, H.R. 1100, 109th Cong. (2005); see also Defense of Marriage Act, 28 U.S.C., section 1738C (2000); James P. George, 鈥淐ivil Law, Procedure, and Private International Law: Access to Justice, Costs, and Legal Aid,鈥 American Journal of Comparative Law 54 (2006): 315 n. 5.

13 Pledge Protection Act, H.R. 2028, 108th Cong. (2004), 109th Cong. (H.R. 2389), 110th Cong. (H.R. 699).

14 Ten Commandments Defense Act, H.R. 2045, 108th Cong. (2003).

15 H.R. 724; H.R. 699, 110th Congress (2007).

16 Ex parte McCardle, 74 U.S. 506 (1869).

17 See Nixon v. United States, 506 U.S. 224 (1993). A federal judge who was convicted at a criminal trial of making false statements before a federal grand jury sought judicial review of his removal from office. He claimed that the Senate had failed to 鈥渢ry鈥 him within the meaning of the Impeachment Clause. (See U.S. Const., article I, section 3.) The Supreme Court held that Nixon鈥檚 challenge presented a nonjusticiable political question because the Impeachment Clause also granted the Senate 鈥渟ole鈥 power to try impeachments. As such, judicial review of senatorial impeachment proceedings is inappropriate.

18 Don Van Natta, Jr., 鈥淛udges Defend A Colleague From Attacks,鈥 The New York Times, March 29, 1996.

19 See United States v. Bayless, 913 F. Supp. 232 (S.D.N.Y. 1996), overruled by United States v. Bayless, 921 F. Supp. 211 (S.D.N.Y. 1996); see also Robert Gearty and Tracy Connor, 鈥淛udge: Keep Cons Cool,鈥 New York Daily News, July 28, 2004.

20 See Anthony Lewis, 鈥淎n Independent Judiciary,鈥 St. Louis University Law Journal 43 (1999): 292.

21 Stephen B. Burbank, 鈥淭he Past and Present of Judicial Independence,鈥 Judicature 80 (1996): 117鈥118.

22 Michael R. Belknap, 鈥淔rom Pound to Harley: The Founding of AJS,鈥 Judicature 72 (1988): 81.

23 Ibid.; William G. Ross, 鈥淭he Questioning of Supreme Court Nominees at Senate Confirmation Hearings: Proposals for Accommodating the Needs of the Senate and Ameliorating the Fears of the Nominees,鈥 Tulane Law Review 62 (1987): 119.

24 Nomination of Ruth Bader Ginsburg, to Be Associate Justice of the Supreme Court of the United States, Hearings Before the Committee on the Judiciary, United States Senate, 103rd Cong. (1993), 145.

25 Jonah Goldberg, 鈥淪enate 鈥楽how Trial鈥 is Product of a Too-Powerful Court,鈥 USA Today, January 11, 2006.

26 Marcia Davis, 鈥淔or Democrats, A Most Tender Roast of Alito,鈥 The Washington Post, January 11, 2006.

27 See William G. Ross, 鈥淭he Judicial Appointments Process: The Questioning of Lower Federal Court Nominees During the Senate Confirmation Process,鈥 William & Mary Bill of Rights Journal 10 (2001): 119鈥120.

28 Diarmuid F. O鈥橲cannlain, 鈥淭oday鈥檚 Senate Confirmation Battles and the Role of the Federal Judiciary,鈥 Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 27 (2003): 174.

29 536 U.S. 765 (2002).

30 Ibid., 807 n. 1 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting).

31 Ibid., 783 n. 11 (emphasis in original).

32 Stenberg v. Carhart, 530 U.S. 914 (2000), which holds that a Nebraska statute criminalizing partial-birth abortions was unconstitutional; Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 577 (2003), which declares unconstitutional a statute that criminalized homosexual conduct; Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 575鈥578 (2005), which outlaws execution of persons who were under eighteen when their crimes were committed; and Atkins v. Virginia, 536 U.S. 304, 316 n. 21 (2002), which bans execution of mentally retarded defendants.

33 See, for example, Catherine Crier, 鈥淲hat Conservatives See as the 鈥楻ight鈥 Stuff,鈥 USA Today, November 3, 2005; Christopher P. Banks, 鈥淩eversals of Precedent and Judicial Policy-Making: How Judicial Conceptions of Stare Decisis in the U.S. Supreme Court Influence Social Change,鈥 Akron Law Review 32 (1999): 247, 249: 鈥淸T]he ruling [of the Rehnquist Court] in [several cases] disclose[s] that the Rehnquist Court is engaging in a conservative brand of judicial activism鈥; see also United States v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549 (1995), which strikes down the Gun-Free School Zones Act of 1990; United States v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598 (2000), which holds the civil remedy provision of the Violence Against Women Act unconstitutional; and Board of Trustees v. Garrett, 531 U.S. 356 (2001), which deems rights and remedies in the Americans with Disabilities Act unconstitutional as applied against states.

34 Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45 (1905) (Holmes, J., dissenting): 鈥淭his case is decided upon an economic theory which a large part of the country does not entertain. . . . The Fourteenth Amendment does not enact Mr. Herbert Spencer鈥檚 Social Statics. . . . [A] constitution is not intended to embody a particular economic theory, whether of paternalism and the organic relation of the citizen to the State or of laissez faire鈥; see also Christopher Wolfe, 鈥淢oving Beyond Rhetoric,鈥 Florida Law Review 57 (2005): 1080: 鈥淸N]either does [the Constitution] enact John Rawls鈥檚 A Theory of Justice or Ronald Dworkin鈥檚 Taking Rights Seriously. There is no requirement of moral neutrality in the Constitution, which left to the states the police powers to protect the safety, health, welfare, and morality of the community鈥; Keith Burgess-Jackson, 鈥淥ur Millian Constitution: The Supreme Court鈥檚 Repudiation of Immorality as a Ground of Criminal Punishment,鈥 Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics, and Public Policy 18 (2004): 409: 鈥淸T]he recent Supreme Court decision on sodomy, Lawrence v. Texas, shows that it all but enacts John Stuart Mill鈥檚 On Liberty.鈥

35 PDK Labs., Inc. v. U.S. DEA, 362 F.3d 786, 799 (D.C. Cir. 2004) (Roberts, J., concurring): 鈥淸T]he cardinal principle of judicial restraint 鈥 if it is not necessary to decide more, it is necessary not to decide more 鈥 counsels us to go no further.鈥

36 Michael D. Weiss and Mark W. Bennett, 鈥淣ew Federalism and State Court Activism,鈥 Memphis State University Law Review 24 (1994): 260, which cites Carl T. Bogus, 鈥淧istols, Politics & Products Liability,鈥 University of Cincinnati Law Review 59 (1991): 1157.

37 Thomas L. Jipping, 鈥淟egislating from the Bench: The Greatest Threat to Judicial Independence,鈥South Texas Law Review 43 (2001): 145.

38 Luke Bierman, 鈥淟egal Development: Preserving Power in Picking Judges: Merit Selection for the New York Court of Appeals,鈥 Albany Law Review 60 (1996): 355.

39 Jipping, 鈥淟egislating from the Bench,鈥 150.

40 Delivered at the Annual Meeting of the American Bar Association in August 1895; revised and published in the American Law Register and Review 43 (9) (1895): 577.