Good work, from Homer to today
Work has long been understood as an ethical practice within a more comprehensive moral economy. Yet students of the modern professions have often ignored the ethical aspects of work. One can therefore only applaud contemporary reform efforts like the GoodWork Project that attempt to understand the specific moral economy of the professions. Effective projects for the reform of work have generally needed to acknowledge not only professionals鈥 ideologies and practices, but also the social institutions and forces that inform them. Only in this way have reformers been able to determine the genuine nature of the problems that undermine good work.
In modern times especially, the challenge of work goes deeper than the moral formation of single individuals. As Karl Marx, 脡mile Durkheim, and Max Weber well understood, we moderns live in a social climate that increasingly and systematically takes control over the conditions of meaningful and responsible work from those who work鈥揺ven within the professions. One implication of their theories is clear: unless the social climate is transformed, merely exhorting students in professional schools to 鈥榙o good鈥 is not likely to produce truly good work.
Advice on how to do good work has been part of Western culture since at least Hesiod鈥檚 Works and Days. The Greek notion of 鈥榚xcellence鈥欌补谤别迟茅 from Ares, the Greek god of war鈥揹ates back to Homer and an era when aristocrats, the aristoi, or 鈥榖est,鈥 assumed that they alone were excellent in the profession that mattered most, that of arms. On the basis of its martial virtue, the Homeric aristocracy justified its superiority to itself and to the common people whose labor sustained its power and wealth.
Aristocratic power and self-conceptions did not go unchallenged, however, as economic growth and technological developments enabled the lower classes to assume an ever-more important role in the waging of war and the defense of society. During struggles over the arbitrariness of aristocratic rule in the seventh and sixth centuries B.C., another ethical conception emerged among the Greeks, associated with 诲颈办茅, or justice. The new ideal introduced a conception of responsibility that went far beyond the tribal loyalty at issue in Homeric 补谤别迟茅. 顿颈办茅 became a social rallying cry, changing the relations between the traditional ruling classes and those they administered.
. . .